Biopiracy refers to the
exploitation of
developing nations and
indigenous farmers through
genetics patents. Often
plants developed over the
centuries by the methods of
traditional agriculture in the
third world are used by first-world
corporations as the basis of patented plants or
inventions. Many people, myself included, feel this to be an
unacceptable situation.
Biopiracy is also a book by Indian author Vandana Shiva, on the subject of biopiracy. The title (and the term itself) turns our usual interpretation of `piracy' (in an IP context) on its head: rather than indicating the violation of `intellectual' `property', the term refers to the IP itself.
I wrote a paper on this topic for a political science course (PS 212, Politics of the Third World, at the University of Kentucky, prof. Dr
James Schlicht). This is one of the better papers I've written;
unlike most of my writings, I spent a great deal of time and effort
on this one.
Introduction
For people in most of the world,
agriculture is one of life's most
important
activities. In addition to providing
sustenance and
income,
farming and related activities lie at the center of the
community and the
society in general.
Anthropologists cite
agriculture as one of the most important factors leading to the
development of
civilisation.
In parts of the world, though, the situation is different.
Throughout the so-called ``industrialised'' world, agriculture has
been in large part taken over by large corporations. Significant
portions of the population go through their entire lives performing
no agricultural tasks beyond maintaining a garden.
The major reason for this transformation has been the
development of agricultural technology. Advances such as
mechanical harvesting, pesticides and herbicides, and genetic
engineering have produced crops of higher yield, allowing a
much smaller group of farmers to provide more food. In this
paper, we concern ourselves with genetic engineering, and
especially with its use by the industrial world in exploiting the
developing world and traditional agriculturalists there.
The primary means of exploitation has been the patent. The
patent as we know it today is primarily a U.S. invention, though
based upon earlier English and European ``letters
patent'' granting monopolies in certain fields
(Shiva). In the United States, patents are
covered by Title 35 of the U.S. Code; notably for our purposes,
Chapter 10 of that Title describes the
conditions under which an invention may be patented, while Chapter 15 allows plants to be patented
(Cornell). Basically, three standard
criteria exist for patents: the invention must be new,
useful, and non-obvious (RAFI, ``Enola
Bean'').
Over the past twenty years, the U.S. Patent and Trademark Office
has seen a large number of patents on genetic
material---especially, but by no means entirely, on plants.
However, most of these plants are based on varieties originally
cultivated in the Third World. According to Mr. Antonio Jacanimijoy, in a presentation before the
World Intellectual Property Organization's Roundtable on
Intellectual Property and Indigenous Peoples, ``the fact that just
one per cent of all patents in the world are granted to persons from
underdeveloped countries, and on the other hand the fact that 90
per cent of germ plasm, the basis for genetic improvement
programs, comes from underdeveloped countries, gives us a clear
idea of the intellectual property system responding to the
interests of a specific sector.'' In other words, the Third
World is being exploited to the benefit of multinational and other corporations in the U.S and
Europe.
Though other systems, such as the wou ``patent'' system of
the Mandang people of New Guinea (Cleveland) exist and have long existed in the developing
world, the most common intellectual property system for
agriculture in the developing world has been the common-heritage
system (Shiva). Under this system, plant
varieties and seeds are considered to be the ``common heritage
of humankind''. If this system were universally held, a claim to a
monopoly on the breeding, development, sale, and use of a
plant would be considered preposterous and morally
reprehensible. Unfortunately, the industrialised world has long
been moving away from this system.
Examples
One of the most
notorious examples of
biopiracy is the
neem
tree (
Azadirachta indica A. Juss.) of
India. Known in
Sanskrit as
sarva roga nivarini (``the
curer of all
ailments''), this
tree has been a part of
Indian culture for
thousands of years. Its finds use as a
pesticide (
Immaraju),
antiseptic,
medicine,
contraceptive
(
Garg), and
soap. The
neem tree was
developed over the course of
centuries by means of
traditional
plant breeding.
In 1985, the U.S. firm Vikwood, Ltd. received U.S. patent
4,556,562 on a ``storage stable neem extract''. A few years
later, it sold this patent to W.R. Grace and Company. Later, in
1995, W.R. Grace and Company obtained U.S. patent 5,411,736, on a
method of using neem oil as an insecticide (Delphion). Although W.R. Grace and Company claims that the
extract is produced using newly-developed techniques, and that the
patent only covers extracts so processed, there is much reason to
be suspicious. First of all, the originality of the method is
not entirely clear. Second, even if the method were original,
the vast majority of the work leading up to this patent was the
traditional agriculture which bred the neem tree as we
know it today.
In 1995, in response to the actions of these corporations and other
ones, the upper house of the Indian parliament forced
the government to table a ``patent amendment bill''. This
reaction was a risky one; the bill was intended to make India
compliant with the WTO's and GATT's rules concerning
intellectual property, and the refusal to pass it could very
well have lead the ejection of India from those organisations
(Shiva 158). However, the Indian government
chose to defend the rights of its own people rather than blindly
support this multinational corporation. Because of the
tabling of that bill, India does not at the moment allow
agricultural product patents (Shiva 158).
For that, India is to be commended.
Another example is the Enola bean, produced by POD-NERS, L.L.C.
This bean is based on the Azufrado bean of Mexico; both have
the taxonomic designation Phaseolus vulgaris. In 1994,
Larry Proctor, president of POD-NERS, bought beans in Mexico;
after two years of selecting yellow seeds from those beans and
breeding them, he obtained a strain that produced a `uniform
and stable population' of yellow bean seeds. In 1999, he obtained
U.S. patent 5,894,079, which covers any Phaseolus vulgaris
beans coloured a particular shade of yellow (Delphion)---despite the fact that Azufrado beans other than
those bred by Proctor often have that colour. Since he was
awarded the patent, Proctor has filed suit against two importers
of yellow Azufrado beans, claiming patent infringement
(RAFI, ``Enola Bean'').
A third example is basmati rice. Any fan of Indian cuisine is
no doubt encountered this fragrant long-grained rice. In 1997,
the company RiceTec, Inc. obtained U.S. patent 5,663,484. This
patent covers a number of lines of basmati rice (Delphion). Thus, by breeding existing strains of basmati
rice, developed by traditional agricultural methods in India, and
protected by no international intellectual property law, RiceTec
obtained what the USPTO views as a patentable product. Again,
the Indian government responded. Under the auspices of Indian
biodiversity legislation, Indian Attorney General Soli Sorabjee
claimed that ``the Government had already taken steps to challenge
the grant of patent'' for these strains of basmati rice (Maharaj).
There are a number of other cases of genetics information produced
by centuries of traditional agriculture suddenly being patented by
multinational corporations. Most, but not all, of the example
come from southern and southeast
Asia. For example, Monsanto has a U.S. patent (5,159,135) which covers all genetically-engineered
cotton; L'Oreal, the French cosmetics company, has patented
the use of kava to prevent hair loss, and a number of
organisations (the U.S. National Institute of Health, the
U.S. Army, and New York University) have patents on the use of
bitter melon in treating HIV (RAFI,
``Patents Out of Control'').
There is another, even more disturbing, application of
intellectual property law to developing countries. A number of
multinational corporations hold patents on human genetic material,
often obtained from indigenous peoples. Typically, those whose
blood, tissue, and hair is harvested are poorly, if at all,
compensated. Although the U.S. National Institute of Health
NIH), in response to increasing pressure from activist groups,
recently adopted a new policy of not seeking patents on human
genetic material identified there, a number of private
corporations still do seek and receive such patents. Companies
such as Biocytes, Human Genome Sciences, and Flinders Medical
Centre continue to receive patents on genetic material to which
they have no moral claim (RAFI, ``Patents
Out of Control'').
Even ignoring the issue of patents, it is not at all clear that
multinational corporations have the right to harvest human
genetic material. Typically, this material will be used to
develop medicines. This would under most circumstances be an
admirable cause; however, the resulting drugs are typically so
expensive that those very people who contributed their genetic
information to the production of the drugs are unable to afford
them (Davis 31).
The benefits of the appropriation, therefore, fall primarily on the
developed world and very little to those contributing the most important
part: the genetic code for the chemicals the patents
describe.
Views
It may be interesting to consider the
views of various
schools of
international politics on the subject of the
patenting of life
from developing countries. Additionally,
anthropologists have
something to say on the matter.
We first consider modernisation theorists.
Here, we find something of a contradiction. As proponents of
liberal economic theory, they usually side against government
intervention, leaning towards a laissez-faire economic system.
However, they are not nearly so anti-regulation when it comes to
patents. Modernisation theorists in general view patents as a
necessary means of protecting the rights of corporations
to their innovations. They, in general, see no reason to consider
genetic material to be an exception (Novak).
According to these scholars, the patent is one of the tools
which has helped build the industrialised world. By protecting
the rights of inventors, so they claim, patents have encouraged
innovation. Patents may thus serve as a means of helping develop
local industry in the Third World. They do not claim that
industrialised countries should be patenting genetic material
from developing countries---rather, that developing countries
should develop patents in defense. Modernisation
theorists generally view the common-heritage system an outmoded
relic which is applied too loosely.
Dependency theorists and world system theorists view things differently. According
to them, patents are yet another method used by the industrialised
or ``core'' countries to maintain dominance over the developing
world or ``periphery''. By patenting Third-World genetic
material, multinational corporations are stripping indigenous
peoples of the rights to their centuries of work. In
addition, by selling products based on those plants back to the
countries in which they originated, multinational corporations are
ensuring their economic dominance.
Dependency, or dependencia, scholars usually do not
feel that patents are an effective or appropriate means of
combating patents. To the contrary, they are quite likely to
suggest that the common-heritage system be given more credence
in international law. Any other result will do nothing but rob
traditional agriculturalists of work that is rightfully theirs.
The third important school of international politics is
classical Marxism. Marxists, in general, see patents as an
individual state's means of furthering the interests of its
industrialists (the receivers of the patents) at the expense of
its workers (those who actually develop the patents). In this
respect, the international situation is simply an extension of
this behaviour to the global level.
These scholars, who typically believe that developing nations
must go through the intermediate stage of capitalism before
arriving at a just economic system, may side with modernisation
theorists in suggesting that Third-World corporations obtain
their own patents on the material; even though this may be
exploitive of traditional farmers, this is an exploitation
that cannot be avoided---and better that they be exploited by
firms within their own nation (which will eventually be able to
share their profits with said farmers) than by a multinational
corporation.
Finally, it may be instructive to look at the opinions of
anthropologists on the matter. Anthropologists studying the
developing world are in a unique position to comment on the
importance of agriculture in that part of the world, and upon
the dangerous influence of industrial-world laws and politics.
In one article, two anthropologists suggest approaching the
problem from the perspectives of ``free access'', ``farmers'
rights'', ``cultural rights'', ``human rights'', and
``environmental rights'' (Cleveland 489-492).
They, in general, feel that patents and trademarks on plants
developed primarily by traditional agriculture serve to objectify
indigenous cultures.
Solutions
It should be obvious that some
solution to the current
situation
is required. Under the current
system,
multinational
corporations are making tremendous
profits from
patents on
genetic information they played only a small
rôle in developing.
Wealth, in the form of
knowledge, is being
plundered from the
developing world. The developing world is as a result losing its
ability to
assert itself
internationally---these patents make
populations, and thus
governments,
dependent on
multinational
corporations.
One possibility is that Third-World governments condemn and
ignore these patents. India has done this with the neem
tree. Unfortunately, such methods may well lead to retaliation
by industrial nations, organisations such as the WIPO, and
multinational corporations. Additionally, this solution
still allows multinational corporations to use their patents to
ensure monopoly in other nations' markets---thus preventing
the originating nation from exporting the product. While some
scholars would argue that developing nations should cease
exports and become entirely self-sufficient, most are not so
revolutionary. This solution is thus not a feasible one.
Another possibility is an improved review process in patent
offices worldwide. Under this solution, industrial countries
would simply not grant patents on genetic material which has
been developed primarily by traditional agriculture. Corporations
and research institutions would have to show a significant
improvement upon the original material before they could be granted
a patent. This is the way the patent system was intended to work,
and the way it theoretically should. However, the large number of
patents considered by such agencies as the U.S. Patent and Trademark
Office tends to lead to a poor review process.
Some would go further and ban genetics patents outright. As an
example, ``one meeting of indigenous peoples in the Pacific
called for the establishment of a treaty declaring the Pacific
region a `lifeforms-patent-free zone' '' (Cleveland 487). Proponents of this approach claim that, by
patenting DNA, corporations are obtaining monopolies on
information developed almost entirely by nature. Plant and
animal breeding may serve to combine this information in new
ways, but the information is still fundamentally not technological
in origin. Another argument is that genetics patents in general
work against the developing world, and that is difficult or
impossible to develop a system of genetics patents that would not
have this problem. For example, Henk Hobbelink lists as one of
twelve reasons for opposing genetics patents that ``If the
patenting of life forms is accepted. . . the third world will
increasingly lose access to scientific information and technological
transfer'' (Hobbelink).
Opponents of this view claim that genetics patents are necessary
to encourage biotechnology research. Whether biotechnology
research is always desirable is, of course, a question for
debate; however, that question is outside the scope of this
paper. Suffice it to say that the probability of industrial
corporations and governments accepting a ban on genetics
patents is minimal.
A fourth solution would be for third-world countries to adopt
their own patent systems (van Wijk). They
could then allow traditional farmers to obtain patents on plant
strains developed by them. However, there are some problems with
this approach. According to one observer, ``industrial-world
intellectual property mechanisms are generally inappropriate for
protecting the intellectual property rights of indigenous
farmers'' (Cleveland 477) and ``Use of these
patent mechanisms would place indigenous peoples in an arena
dominated by industrial-country governments, corporations,
and legal systems'' (Cleveland 487). In
addition, there is still the question of whether a single farmer
(or even a group of farmers) should be able to claim patent on
plants developed primarily by means of traditional agriculture
over a period of centuries. One possible solution is for the
government to itself to claim such patents, holding
them in trust for the entire population, and use them only for
defense against industrial-world patents; or for those
governments to allow collective patents by groups of indigenous
farmers (Shiva 157). Such measures, however,
would require much more careful analysis before they are
implemented---if the industrial world would accept them at all.
A final solution is to modify patent law to incorporate, or at
least to work with, the common-heritage system. Patent law could
recognise that certain plant materials belonged to the common
heritage of society, and that, short of genetic modifications
such as recombinant DNA techniques, plants based on these
strains should not be made proprietary. Some will argue that
this proposal does not go far enough---that it would still allow
industrial-world corporations to use third-world plants and
recombinant DNA to produce patentable inventions. However, such a
compromise is likely to be the only way to obtain the
cooperation of industrial nations. In addition, it would still
allow traditional farmers to use their existing crop varieties
without fear of having to pay royalties in the future. It will be
up to third-world nations and the farmers themselves to ensure
that they do not in other ways become dependent on patented
plants.
Conclusion
Biopiracy is a
growing problem, and it is obvious that some
steps must be taken to
defend the
rights of
developing nations
and
indigenous farmers. Whether the
solution involves improving
the
patent review process,
banning genetics patents, or
developing some new mix of the
common-heritage system and
modern
intellectual-property law, it is clear that some
change is
necessary. While
developing nations must take a stand for
themselves (and
India in particular is
to be commended for doing
so), it is also up to us, as
members of the industrial world, to
make sure that such
solutions are
implemented. The
United
States is home to most of the world's largest
multinational
corporations, and to most of those
corporations that obtain
patents on
genetic material to which they have
no right. Only
by
boycotting those
companies and
petitioning our
elected representatives can we ensure a
fair and
prosperous
future for
indigenous peoples throughout the
world.
Works Cited
Cleveland, David A. and Stephen C. Murray. ``The World's
Crop
Genetic Resources and the
Rights of Indigenous Farmers.''
Current Anthropology Vol. 38 No. 4, Aug.-Oct. 1997.
United States Code. Jan. 1999. Cornell University Legal
Information Institute. 4 Apr. 2000
http://www4.law.cornell.edu/uscode/
Davis, I. J., ``A Deadly Dearth of Drugs.'' Mother Jones,
February 2000.
Garg, Sanjay, G.P. Talwar, and S.N. Upadhyay. ``Identification and
Characterization of the Immunomodulatory Fraction from Neem Seed
Extract Responsible for Long-Term Antifertility Activity''. Neem
and Environment. Eds. R.P. Singh, M.S. Chari, A.K. Raheja,
and W. Kraus. Lebanon, N.H.: Science Publishers, Inc., 1996.
Hobbelink, Henk. Biotechnology and the Future of World
Agriculture. London: Zed Books, Ltd., 1989.
Delphion Intellectual Property Network. April 2000. Delphion. 4 April 2000 http://www.delphion.com/
Immaraju, John et. al. ``Efficacy Profile of a Commercial Neem
Insecticide''. In Singh et al, 1996.
Jacanimijoy, Antonio. Initiatives for Protection of Rights of
Holders of Traditional Knowledge, Indigenous Peoples and Local
Communities. July 1998. World Intellectual Property
Organization. 4 April 2000
http://www.wipo.int/eng/meetings/1998/indip/rt98_4e.htm
Maharaj, Jai. ``US Patent for `Karela', `Jamun', `Brinjal'
Alleged.'' Online Posting. 13 Mar. 2000. misc.legal
USENET group.
Novak, Michael. The Fire of Invention, the Fuel of Interest: On
Intellectual Property. Washington, D.C.: The American
Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 1996.
Rural Advancement Foundation International (RAFI). 4 Apr. 2000
http://www.rafi.org/.
Shiva, Vandana and Radha Holla-Bhar. ``Piracy By Patent: The Case
of the Neem Tree''. The Case Against the Global Economy and for
a Turn to the Local. Eds. Jerry Mander and Edward Goldsmith.
San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1996. 146--159.
van Wijk, Jeroen, Joel I. Cohen, and John Komen. Intellectual
Property Rights for Agricultural Biotechnology; Options and
Implications for Developing Countries. The Hague: International
Service for National Agricultural Research, 1993.